David Javidzad
GSI: Jerilyn Sambrooke
Rhetoric 103A
26 November 2016
Figurative Reading of Encomium of Helen, by Gorgias
In
his Encomium of Helen, Gorgias makes an argument for exonerating the infamous,
ancient Homeric character, Helen. The argument proceeds by the logically valid
argument form, constructive dilemma. He infers a conclusion from several
conditional statements, which all have a common consequent, namely that Helen
is innocent (or that we should absolve the character of Helen from her bad
reputation), and adds a set of sufficient conditions to validly imply this
consequent. The argument’s first premise states that if Paris abducted Helen by
force, then she had no intent to cause mischief, and so her departure to Troy
is innocent. Another conditional proposition holds that if Helen had fallen in
love with Paris, then she was guided passionately by a divine force, so she
cannot be blamed for her departure because she was subject to the lure of
divine love, and therefore, her departure to Troy is not worthy of
condemnation. After elaborating on these main conditional statements, and
introducing more premises for support, along with concessions and
qualifications, Gorgias adds the final premise to validate his conclusion:
“[Helen was] either passionately in love or persuaded by discourse or abducted
by force or constrained by divine constraints…” (Section 20). This disjunctive
statement eliminates alternate reasoning and says that any of these conditions
are true then the consequent must be too; it justifies the necessary condition
of all the conditional statements, leading to Gorgias’s main conclusion: Helen
is innocent and must be absolved of blame. Logical validity, the strength of
the relationship between premises and conclusion, and good structure, however, are not the only aspects that make Gorgias’s
argument so persuasive, compelling, and eloquent. He employs figurative
language by way of allegory, analogy, and symbolism, rendering the argument
interesting and worthy of attention and acclaim.
Defending
the art of persuasion throughout the text, Gorgias constructs an analogy
between drugs, or pharmacopoeia, and
rhetoric. As opposed to using metaphor or simile here, which less transparently
mask the underlying referent, he declares an analogy, explicitly mentioning the
relationship of each part to each other: “The power of discourse stands in the
same relation to the soul's organization as the pharmacopoeia does to the
physiology of bodies” (14). He goes on to elaborate the ways in which different
medicines can heal different ailments or be appropriate or inappropriate
depending on different situations. This has strong argumentative effects as it
establishes the relativity of rhetoric’s just usage. Rather than being an art
that universally falls into either a just or unjust category, he argues, rhetoric
can be used properly, misused, and abused. This establishes a distance from
those who unjustly use it, and adds moral value to Gorgias’s apparent usage of
persuasive techniques, rendering him one of the “just” rhetoricians, accomplishing
the task of removing negative bearings on an innocent person’s reputation.
Helen
herself is the main figure of the text. Literally, Gorgias is using Helen, who
at that point in time exists only as a mythical or historical figure, to
accomplish a great rhetorical challenge. In the context of ancient Greece, the
perception of Helen as a historical figure was conventionally one that received
condemnation and accusation. Similarly, due in part to Socrates and other Greek
thinkers who dismissed ‘sophistry,’ Greeks did not perceive favorably the art of
persuasive speaking. Throughout the text, there is a subtext in which Gorgias,
a proponent of rhetoric and one of Socrates’s challengers, argues that rhetoric and eloquence in speech is worthy of celebration (encomium), and the
defamation it has attained (through Socrates or otherwise) is unwarranted. Gorgias
will purport to exonerate Helen and rhetoric simultaneously, establishing an interchangeability
between Helen and persuasion as logical inferences from his reasoning.
Using
the figure of Helen allegorically, Gorgias implicitly and explicitly celebrates
rhetoric’s power— explicitly by mentioning, demonstrating, and boasting that he
is able to accomplish such a great feat (namely, absolving Helen, a seemingly impossible
task) using only words and eloquence; and implicitly by veiling the argument
about rhetoric itself behind the figure of Helen. At the end of the argument,
for example, after having stated his conclusion, he proceeds to call her his “plaything,”
and, as if to say ‘Voila!’ he
asserts, “I have removed infamy from a woman” (21). These final remarks reveal
Gorgias’s manipulation of the figure of Helen and expose the intersection
between Helen and the implicit argument about rhetoric.
Gorgias
introduces the argument by stating, “It being required of the same man both to
speak straight and to refute crooked speech, one should refute those blaming
Helen” (2). This is where “well-speaking” and Helen are first paralleled. He
uses the requirement of man to speak well as a justification for his taking on
this task, and then claims to “put an end to ignorance” (2) this way. Then, establishing
a parallel between Helen’s beauty and Gorgias’s experience with attracting
crowds with his orations, Gorgias mentions, “She produced the greatest erotic
desires in most men. For one body many bodies of men came together” (4). Here, the
effects of Helen’s notorious beauty represent the persuasive, potent appeal of
words and eloquence.
In
regards to the possibility that Helen could have been deceived by persuasive
discourse, Gorgias contends that discourse is powerful and she was victimized
by its use (or misuse) rather than an offender herself. This figures in the
argument is several ways: On the surface, it is another reason for exonerating
Helen, pitying her rather than condemning her, and this adds value to Gorgias’s
accomplishment, which, in turn, bolsters his implicit argument about rhetoric.
He is also explicitly mentioning, however, the immense power of persuasive
speaking, and goes on to celebrate its various abilities. In this case, he
presents it as an agent of deception, and he goes on to condemn rhetoric’s
abusers, who, deliberately are not Helen. This figures in the argument as a
concession to critics of persuasion, but does not result in weakening the
argument, for he will continue to successfully absolve Helen, who represents
rhetoric, of ill repute.
By
referring to the appeal of beauty in Helen, her vulnerability to the persuasion
of others, and by exhibiting his own rhetorical prowess, Gorgias simultaneously
defends rhetoric in the context of Socratic denigration of it and accomplishes a
self-promoting triumph in exonerating Helen.
No comments:
Post a Comment